How to value international law as a classical liberal

I live in the ‘City of International Peace and Justice’ according to the city marketing of the municipality of The Hague. There is some truth in it, as the International Court of Justice, the International Criminal Court and temporary courts such as the International Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugoslavia are all located within the city limits. Yet the supposed relation between peace and justice is of course non-sensical. These international legal institutions may sometimes foster individual and sometimes even county-level justice, yet they have nothing to do with peace. History shows that punishing one war criminal does not prevent others to commit crimes against humanity, and settling a border dispute between two countries does not external effects elsewhere.

This is no surprise to classical liberals, as it confirms to their view on human nature, where emotions ultimately master rationality. This ensures international conflict and war are and will always be a feature in world politics. The most relevant question in international relations is not ‘how can we get rid of international violence and create a peaceful world’, but ‘how can we deal with the inevitable conflict that will be present?’. Perpetual peace is not attainable, perpetual war the norm, although luckily not of all people against all, all of the time. The value of international law is that it is one of the instruments that may channel or once in a while even prevent international conflict.

From a classical liberal perspective, international law is an expression of the common norms in the society of states, although without ultimate arbiter. Like law in domestic politics, international law must be restricted to the protection of the individual natural rights. And as in domestic politics, this has not been the case. International law has also exploded, while in many instances international law takes precedence in domestic legal order, which makes it even more important to limit its expansion.

For example, already Mises and Hayek objected to the explosion of positive international law, including the related establishment of international governmental organizations that occurred from the late nineteenth century onward. For classical liberals most international organizations, often created by governments of non-liberal persuasion, are attempts at constructivism at the international level. Mises and Hayek were also among the first to warn against the extended number of tasks of the League of Nations and both rejected the way the United Nations was set up. Hayek in particular warned against the inclusion of social and economic rights in the Universal Declaration on Human Rights and was very critical of the International Labor Organization.

Consequently, classical liberals should favor the abolition of international governmental organizations with tasks that extend beyond the principles of the limited state, spontaneous order, and the protection of individual natural rights. This is not a call for isolationism as there is also common sense in some international state cooperation and sometimes even a need for an international bureaucracy. I propose as a rule of thumb: if there is no need for state interference domestically, there is no need for international state action either. The exceptions are some tasks that follow specifically from international circumstances. Without going into details, this principle may, for example, lead to classical liberal support for aforementioned International Criminal Court and the special UN war tribunals, as the best way to punish people who infringed natural rights. But it may also call for the abolition of organizations that interfere with free markets and capitalism, such as the World Bank, the ILO, and the International Monetary Fund.

In short: some international law is beneficial, but most constitutes unwanted international constructivism.

10 thoughts on “How to value international law as a classical liberal

  1. “This is no surprise to classical liberals, as it confirms to their view on human nature, where emotions ultimately master rationality.”

    This comment was surprising to me; it seems to run counter to what I see here. Could you or another of the libertarians elaborate?

    • You have to go back to the split between “left” and “right” libertarians to understand this argument. Those on the “left” see emotion as mastering rationality while those on the “right” pretend otherwise.

      Most of us here see emotion as master over rationality, which is why we tend to criticize, say, democracy (see Warren’s great piece and Fred’s great piece for more). You’ll notice that we are not democratic abolitionists, but only that we see major problems associated with “social democracy.”

      A digression: social democracy is not an ideology. It is patchwork of socialism and liberalism that Leftists grappling with the collapse of the USSR have come up with to challenge the supremacy of the liberal’s framework.

      It’s basically a by-product of the liberal framework that attempts to undermine liberalism without attempting to do what socialists in the past attempted to do: abolish it.

      At any rate, when you read most of the stuff here (thanks for doing so, by the way), keeping Dr van de Haar’s observation in mind will go a long way towards helping you better understand our arguments.

      PS: It does not follow that just because emotions rule reason that government is necessary to step in and “help” individuals out. After all, government itself is composed of – say it with me – beings that are largely governed by emotions rather than reason. This is why libertarians advocate that the state do as little as possible (if anything at all!)

  2. I was indeed a bit short on this point. Besides Brandon’s remarks I would like to add, that ‘the view of human nature’ is a core question in (political) philosophy. It has been since the Enlightenment in all its varieties. In essence it is about what constitutes a human: what are the different kinds of emotions, what role do they play in instigating human behaviour, how about the capacity to think and use the brain, et cetera. Hume’s ‘Treatise on Human Nature’ and Smith’s ‘Theory of Moral Sentiment’ are both about exactly this issue. As Brandon wrote American liberals (social liberals in Europe) think that the ratio can overcome all emotions, at the end of the day. Therefore they have faith that ‘logical and rational solutions’ will ultimately prevail. For example the faxt that war is costly and disatrous. That is the truth, but it does not make war dissappear, because not all people are that rational in the deciding moments, or they are just bad people willingly searching confrontation in expectation of other types of gains, et cetra,

    The great thing (at least to me) is that these old insights (and of course Hume and Smith did not invent them either) are now increasingly confirmed by modern psycological research. For example Kahneman, but also Rosen’s ‘War and Human Nature’ and Thayer’s ‘Darwinian International Relations’.

  3. “The great thing (at least to me) is that these old insights (and of course Hume and Smith did not invent them either) are now increasingly confirmed by modern psycological research. For example Kahneman, but also Rosen’s ‘War and Human Nature’ and Thayer’s ‘Darwinian International Relations’.”

    Yes, and work in neurology as well. But I know from personal experience on the blog talking about amygdala highjacking that some flavors of libertarians are reluctant to admit the power of emotion. I’m still sorting through the different variations of libertarianism 😦

  4. Donot be sad, there something to your liking for sure. It is great to wander through the world of ideas, always valuable whereever you end up!

  5. […] So what to do, or aim for, as Western countries? Obviously, most Syrians are better off in a stable situation without war, than with any currently viable alternative. This means that negotiations about cease fires should commence, or at least be fostered, which will then hopefully lead to a permanent settlement. I do not dare to predict how long it will take for this approach to be successful. Yet any alternative is worse. These negotiations, whenever feasible, should have all parties at the table, Assad included. No vetoes against him being part of future talks, as has previously been the case. The man will stay around for a while, and we better get used to the idea. This is surely deplorable, yet inevitable. The situation in Syria shows once again the ugliness of international politics, with very limited roles for international law and justice. […]

Please keep it civil